Picturing the Human (Body and Soul):
A Reading of Blade Runner
by Dr Stephen Mulhall
1) Acknowledging Human Mortality
It would seem advisable to begin this interpretation of the film with
an uncontroversial claim, so let us note at the outset that Blade Runner
is explicitly concerned with the question of what it is to be a human
being: indeed, since it ignores many of the expectations usually catered
to by films in the genre of detective-thriller (e.g. complexities of plotting
or concealment of the identities and purposes of the criminals) and of
science fiction (e.g. focusing on technology rather than people, or employing
exotic and alien backdrops) in order to allow its thematic questioning
of humanity to dominate the sequence of events, it might be more accurate
to describe the film as being obsessed with the matter obsessed in the
way the leader of the replicants is obsessed with his quest for life,
for a life which is on a par with that of human beings. To show that Roy
Baty misconceives this quest as one for more life as if a replicant might
become human by living longer is the goal of the film.
In the course of this quest, many erroneous answers to the original question
are canvassed and rejected. By endowing the replicants with intelligence
levels and physical strength at least equal to that of any human being,
it is made very clear from the beginning that the possession of such capacities
goes no way towards settling the ontological status of their possessors;
in fact, rather than confirming the replicants as candidates for humanity,
the fine-honed perfection and virtuosity of their physical and mental
skills tends to cast doubt upon their candidature this, I take it, is
why those scenes in which the replicants manifest their invulnerability
to extremes of heat and cold (in the hygienic chill of the eye laboratory
or the hot water in which J. F. Sebastian boils his egg) tend to alienate
the viewer from Leon and Pris.
In this way, the film leads us to ask whether what the replicants lack
is the frailty of human flesh and blood. The question becomes most insistent
in the sequences dealing with J. F. Sebastian and his replicant visitors
in the abandoned Bradbury buildings: the superhuman flawlessness of Roy
and Pris stands out more strongly when contrasted with the physical decrepitude
inflicted on Sebastian by a genetic flaw known as Methuselah Syndrome
accelerated aging. (Roy asks why Sebastian is staring at his visitors,
and is told: "Because you're so different, you're so perfect.")
Sebastian's physical inadequacies evoke sympathy but not in Roy or Pris;
the way in which they manipulate him as a means towards their goal of
confronting Tyrell simultaneously confirms the humanity of their victim
and the inhumanity of their attitude towards him perfection seems to signify
difference, as Sebastian implies.
This is not, however, the conclusion that the film determines us to draw;
and to justify this claim we must turn to the thematic relevance of the
violence which is present throughout the narrative. On a first viewing,
the relentless emphasis upon bloodied bodies and brutal physical punishments
which permeates the story and appears to encompass the spectrum of such
possibilities -quite apart from the "retirement" of three replicants,
we are forced to witness an attempted strangulation, savage beatings,
an attack with an iron bar, deliberately broken fingers and a climax of
concentrated physical suffering can strike one as sadistic and verging
upon the obscene. This impression can be altered, however, if one notes
that the characters to whom violence is seen to be done are primarily
Deckard and the replicants. (Tyrell is murdered in a context in which
he has assumed divine rather than human status of which more later and
we never see Sebastian's execution or his corpse.) We shall return to
the significance of Deckard's role as victim later, when we examine the
way in which Blade Runner might be seen as an account of Deckard's education,
of the way in which the replicants (who alone are his victimizers) teach
him a lesson; but if we set this aside for a moment, then we are required
to account for the fact that the violence portrayed in the film is directed
primarily against non-human characters against those supposedly incapable
of suffering and also lacking that human status which would make the infliction
of pain upon them a moral crime.
What the scenes of violence succeed in eliciting is an instinctive response
to this treatment of the replicants which matches our response to such
treatment when directed against human beings; we see their behavior as
the expression of pain and suffering rather than as an empty mechanical
analogue of such things exhibited by an automaton. The slow-motion presentation
of Zhora's final trajectory through the plate-glass shop-windows is justified
by its achievement in making us accept Deckard's remorse at having to
shoot a woman in the back rather than retiring a replicant; and by the
time Deckard shoots Pris a second time in order to end the mechanical
threshing of her limbs caused by his first shot, we need no dialogue to
tell us that he is in fact putting someone out of her misery. As Roy puts
it: "We're not computers, Sebastian we're physical;" the violence
inflicted upon the replicants drives home the fact that they are embodied,
and thus capable of manifesting the range and complexity of behavior open
to any human being. The empathic claim exerted upon us by those scenes
in which that behavior becomes pain-behavior is what grounds the film's
assumption that it is this aspect of the replicant's embodiment which
is pertinent to their candidature for human status, and not the issue
of whether anything occupies their bodies.
To put this last point more precisely: the way in which the embodied
nature of the replicants is presented in Blade Runner reveals that one
misunderstands the relation between mind and body if one views it from
the Cartesian perspective of an immaterial substance contained within
a material one; this suggests that the domain of the mental is hidden
away behind, and entirely distinct from, that of the body. This film presents
us with entities whose bodies resemble those of human beings in their
form and flexibility, entities who manifest behavior of a complexity and
range which matches that of a human being and on this basis alone, the
viewer is brought to apply to those entities all the psychological concepts
which together constitute the logical space of the mental. Blade Runner
thus makes explicit the fact that the criteria which justify our application
of psychological concepts (our attribution of a mind) are to be found
in behavior of a particular complexity a complexity capable of bearing
the logical multiplicity of those concepts. In the context of a philosophical
seminar, the Cartesian might respond by claiming that such applications
depend upon an argument by analogy and that a grasp of the meaning of
such words presupposes direct acquaintance with the introspectible private
entities and processes which they name; someone impressed by Wittgenstein's
work in this area might attempt to go through the private language argument
in order to reveal the incoherences of private ostensive definition. Rather
than argue towards the conclusions Wittgenstein draws, this film dramatizes
them: it produces conviction in Wittgenstein's remark that "The human
body is the best picture of the human soul" by picturing a body which
resembles a human one in a form and flexibility and thereby eliciting
from the viewer the attitude one adopts towards a human soul.
It is important to recognize that nothing said so far entails that Blade
Runner is committed to a behavioristic conception of psychological phenomena:
in denying a specific interpretation of the inner world of human beings,
one need not collapse the inner into the outer or reduce the one to the
other. The claim is rather that psychological concepts cannot be distinguished
from purely behavioral ones by arguing that they relate only indirectly
to human behavior and refer to hidden ethereal processes; both sets of
concepts relate to the same evidential base (as it were) namely, the behavior
of human beings but they organize that base in significantly different
ways and thereby alter what we see when our perception of things is informed
by either set. The nature of that difference is made clear by the contrast
between Captain Bryant's view of the replicants and the developing perceptions
of Deckard as he approaches his confrontation with Roy: entities perceived
as "skinjobs" can yet attain the status of human beings.
A nagging question remains, however, which might be put in the following
way: which of the two, Deckard and Bryant, is right? How can we know whether
any one of these entities can correctly be regarded as human? The misleading
nature of such questioning is rooted in the way it takes for granted the
concepts of correctness and knowledge. The evidence of the film shows
that it is "correct" to apply psychological concepts to the
replicants in the sense that their behavior satisfies the criteria governing
those concepts; to assume that some further notion of correctness has
yet to be settled presupposes that we might apply those concepts in cases
where our applications are completely justified and yet still be wrong
as if someone could satisfy all our criteria for personhood and yet not
be one. This worry is groundless because incapable of giving any content
to the notion of what it is that this entity has failed to be, given that
our criteria for personhood exhaust what it is to be a person, and that
this entity fulfills all those criteria. One might say that we know all
that there is to know about the replicants which is relevant to their
claim for human status; there is no further fact of the matter being kept
from us. Nothing counts against their being treated as human.
Nothing except the unwillingness or refusal of other human beings to
do so. No accumulation of facts or evidence can force someone to acknowledge
behavior which fulfills all the criteria of pain-behavior as being the
genuine expression of another human being's pain. Captain Bryant is not
ignorant of "the truth" about the replicants he can see everything
that we and Deckard can see; rather, he denies or fails to acknowledge
that truth. Here, however, we should pause to register the inaccuracies
of our talk of truth, for truth relates to concepts of evidence and fact;
the truth is that replicant behavior fulfills all the criteria for e.g.
pain-behavior, anger-behavior, etc, but that truth does not entail that
someone who fails to acknowledge such behavior as genuinely expressive
of a heart and mind is denying any of those facts he is rather adopting
one possible attitude towards the facts. Bryant and Deckard take up opposing
attitudes to the facts with which they are presented; and neither can
be said to be right or wrong in the sense of corresponding or failing
to correspond to those facts. What this entails, however, is that the
humanity of the replicants or indeed of all human beings is in the hands
of their fellows; their accession to human status involves their being
acknowledged as human by others. They can fulfill all the criteria, but
they cannot force an acknowledgement from those around them; and if their
humanity is denied, it withers. As Stanley Cavell would put it, we do
not know that any given entity is a human being; rather, we acknowledge
or deny their humanity in the attitude we adopt towards them <1>.
It is this theme which the film explores in more detail through the relationship
between Deckard and Rachael. Their first meeting takes place across a
Voight-Kampff machine, the equipment used by blade runners to assess a
subject's capillary dilation, blush response, fluctuation of the pupil
and other physiological registers of emotional response the theory being
that replicants lack any empathic attunement with others and thereby betray
their difference from human beings. As Tyrell points out to Deckard, however,
this lack of empathy and the correlative emotional immaturity evinced
by the replicants is purely a function of the decision by their human
makers to restrict their life-span and correspondingly constrain the range
of their memories and experience; Rachael has been "gifted with a
past," a gift which it is hoped will "create a cushion or pillow
for the emotions" but which also entails that Rachael does not "know"
that she is a replicant. For Deckard, Rachael's failure to pass the V-K
test is a simple proof of her non-humanity; he fails to see that his difficulty
in detecting the usual emotional absence in her suggest that this lack
is both contingent and a matter of degree, i.e. that he might regard the
replicants as being children in an emotional sense through no fault of
their own, and thus as being capable of maturity. He also fails to note
that Captain Bryant the sort of lawman who called black men "niggers"
offers standing proof that human beings can lack empathic attunement with
others whilst retaining human status.
We know that Deckard will deny Rachael's humanity that his relationship
towards her will begin by being death-dealing because of the scene in
his apartment block in which she startles him in the elevator: at the
first indication of her presence, he turns his gun on her instinctively.
It becomes clear that this gesture signifies more than the reflexes of
a trained blade runner when she follows him into his apartment in search
of comfort and reassurance against the shock of discovering her status
as a replicant; for Deckard proceeds to take up an attitude towards her
which is as deadly as any gun-shot. He wrenches away from her the pillow
of her past, the experiences transmuted by memory with which Tyrell has
gifted her, by reciting intimate recollections to her face (violating
and expropriating her privacy, her inner life) and informing her that
they belong to Tyrell's niece (alienating her from that which gives a
person any sense of continuity over time a point Locke emphasizes); his
clumsy attempt to back away from the suffering he thereby causes only
makes matters worse by manifesting his inability to care about Rachael
enough to perform this task of reparation with tact and delicacy. In the
end, he wants her to leave his apartment; and Rachael does as he desires.
Their next encounter in the flesh comes after Zhora's death, when Rachael
saves Deckard from Leon's murderous attack. Back in his apartment, Deckard
acknowledges his own feelings to the extent of assuring Rachael who is
now on the run from the authorities that he would never hunt her down
and kill her; but the reason he gives for this decision that he owes her
one reveals the limited nature of that acknowledgement. They are equals
in the way a debtor and his creditor are equals; saving lives is no more
than a business deal, nothing personal is permitted to intrude. This mercenary
implication, together with Deckard's unthinking reference to nerves as
part of the blade runner business when his rescuer is herself not only
part of the business but its essence and victim (retirement is a little
more discomforting than "the shakes"), gives Rachael the anger
necessary to reject the interpretation of their relationship which Deckard
is offering; but her inquiry as to whether Deckard has ever taken the
V-K test himself falls on deaf ears. For the viewer, however, this question
hangs together with the accumulating evidence that the blade runner business
and its barter of life-taking for a living wage is dehumanizing; and we
begin to see the way in which a refusal to acknowledge another's humanity
constitutes a denial of the humanity in oneself.
As this complex scene continues, we are offered some indication that
Deckard's failings are redeemable; for when he wakes to find Rachael playing
the piano and discovers that she did so in order to test the legitimacy
of a memory of piano lessons ("I remember lessons I don't know if
it's me or Tyrell's niece"), his response ("You play beautifully")
manifests precisely the tact and delicacy needed to undo the damage of
his brutal mishandling of this topic earlier. The situation seems ripe
for a full acknowledgement of their feelings for one another, but Rachael
takes fright and is only prevented from leaving the apartment by Deckard
slamming the door. He pushes her against the wall, and initiates the following
dialogue as he advances on her:
Deckard: "You kiss me."
Rachael: "I can't rely on -"
Deckard: "Say 'Kiss me'."
Rachael: "Kiss me."
Deckard: "I want you."
Rachael: "I want you."
Deckard: "Again."
Rachael: "I want you. Put your arms around me..."
This sequence, with its lushly romantic soundtrack, hits a very false
note: Deckard seems to be extracting an acknowledgement by force and thus
not extracting an acknowledgement at all, and the threatening structure
of the scene carries overtones of rape, of a male unable to take no for
an answer. The reality is more complex. We have some grounds for thinking
that at this stage Rachael is indeed denying her true feelings for Deckard;
her problem is not just that she cannot rely on Deckard's feelings, but
also that she feels incapable of staking her life on her own emotions
the revelations about a transplanted personality make her unsure of the
reality of the emotions she feels in a way which is precisely analogous
to her doubts about her capacity to play the piano. To this degree, she
needs help in surmounting this anxiety, and Deckard is the appropriate
person to provide this help; indeed, this is clearly what he takes himself
to be doing in the dialogue quoted above allowing her to acknowledge without
fear the reality of her feelings. The difficulties arise because Deckard
forces the right words into her mouth and thereby violates her autonomy;
Rachael is given a lesson in how to express her inner life, and by the
end of the scene she does learn how to go on and find the appropriate
words unprompted ("Put your hands on me..."), but this learning
process occurs within an overall context of teacher and pupil i.e. of
a power-relationship which fails to allow for the equality of participants.
The way in which Deckard and Rachael here acknowledge their feelings for
one another inevitably prevents a full acknowledgement of Rachael's humanity;
and since it was Deckard who set the terms of this encounter who failed
to find a way of educating Rachael which acknowledged her autonomy the
responsibility for Rachael's failure to be fully respectful of her own
humanity is his.
What is needed is a further and fateful step in Deckard's own education
a lesson which Roy Baty undertakes to deliver in the Bradbury buildings.
We will return to this climactic sequence to trace its contours in some
detail, but for now we should complete our account of the theme of acknowledgement
by considering the alteration in Deckard's relationship with Rachael which
is manifest when he returns to her after Roy's death. His apartment is
quiet, disturbed only by the flicker of a video screen, and he finds Rachael
on a couch completely covered in a sheet; the identification of this sheet
with a shroud is immediate, and when Deckard removes it he seems to be
revealing a corpse. At this point, however, Deckard discovers a way of
addressing Rachael which brings her fully (back) to life one which contrasts
with their previous confrontation beside the closed door of the apartment.
In that encounter they faced one another standing, thus forming a strong
vertical patterning on the screen which emphasized Deckard's superior
height and aggression and reinforced the sense of his domination; in this
scene, he leans over her face from the head of the couch, creating an
equally strong horizontal patterning to their encounter one which does
away with his superiority of height and build and confers a sense of their
profiles being essentially complementary rather than competitive. The
ensuing dialogue matches this sense of achieved equality:
Deckard: "Do you love me?"
Rachael: "I love you."
Deckard: "Do you trust me?"
Rachael: "I trust you."
Rather than forcing words into her mouth by rote, Deckard asks questions
and Rachael is free to choose her answers more precisely, she freely chooses
to acknowledge her love for Deckard, and by creating a conversation in
which Rachael could do this in a way which respects her own autonomy,
Deckard comes to share in the responsibility for their achievement of
equality and the full mutual acknowledgement it permits. These two have
earned their escape from the nightmarish city-scape in which everyone's
humanity is at risk.
Acknowledgement has thus emerged as a central aspect of what might be
termed human flourishing; the possession of human form and behavior of
the requisite complexity can make an entity eligible for treatment as
a human (ie it is a necessary condition for being so treated), but such
entities can only develop in their personhood can only become fully human
if their humanity is acknowledged rather than denied. Blade Runner adds
a further twist to this claim by revealing in Deckard the crippling consequences
for one's own humanity of the failure to acknowledge the humanity of others;
to deny it in others is to deny it in oneself. In tracing out this theme
we have shown how several alternative criteria for humanity specific levels
of intelligence, physical virtuosity, emotional empathy reveal their irrelevance;
and the problems which might have been raised by robots rather than by
replicants (by mechanical entities rather than organisms cloned from genetic
material) are simply by-passed. There remains, however, one other element
of being human with which both the film and the leader of the replicants
are obsessed, an element which must be fitted into our thinking about
this film that of mortality. Part of being human is being mortal; and
Blade Runner attempts to explore the significance of human mortality in
complex ways.
What does it mean to claim that human beings are mortal? If we were to
answer this by means of a contrast with the notion of immortality, then
it would seem that mortality consists in the fact that one does not live
forever that a mortal life must end at some point. This contrast encourages
the view that human beings are mortal because their lives occupy a finite
quantity of time, because their days are numbered and destined to run
out soon after three-score years and ten. Such a view is clearly the one
taken by the replicants in general and Roy Baty in particular; their dangerous
trip back to Earth is motivated by the desire for more life the desire
to extend their allotted span of days until it matches that of a human
being and allows them to go on prosecuting their projects, loves and interests.
Are we to accept the assumption that the replicants are less than human
because their death comes more swiftly and with complete certainty?
It is made very clear in Blade Runner that such an assumption embodies
crucial misunderstandings of the specifically human relation to death;
and these misunderstandings are disinterred and undermined with dizzying
speed in the course of one brief scene. After Deckard has shot Zhora and
is wandering through crowded streets looking for Rachael, he is accosted
by Leon who observed Deckard's execution of his lover and dragged into
an alley, where Leon proceeds to administer a savage beating to the blade
runner. It is, however, the dialogue in this scene which is of most importance:
Leon: "How old am I?"
Deckard: "I don't know."
Leon: "My birthday is April 10th, 2017. How long do I live?"
Deckard: "Four years."
Leon: "More than you. Painful to live in fear, isn't it? Nothing
is worse than having an itch you can't scratch."
Deckard: "I agree."
Leon: "Wake up time to die."
By this stage in the film, our sympathies have been directed towards
the replicants and their desire for a longer life-span; we feel sorry
for them because, unlike us, their genetically-engineered constitution
embodies an ineradicable four-year limit to their existence, and they
know from the moment of their inception the precise date of their death.
Barring accidents, we think, any human being can rely on living far longer
than any replicant. It is precisely this assumption which Leon puts into
question in his interrogation of Deckard, for Leon's ability to kill the
blade runner negates any illusion that a normal human life-span trumps
one with replicant limitations death cannot be kept at a Biblical arms-length.
Indeed, Leon begins to emerge as a figure of real power as he names the
moment of Deckard's death; it seems that the replicants' certainty about
the date of their own end allows them to master and dismiss any fears
about dying, since that fatal possibility is tied down to a specific day
whereas frail human beings, as Deckard is discovering, can never be sure
when their end will come. At this point, however, our impression of replicant
superiority is in turn shown to be an illusion, for Rachael saves Deckard
from execution by shooting Leon in the head thus proving that knowing
the date at which one's death is inevitable is not the same as knowing
when one will die.
The lesson of this scene is clear: mortal finitude should not be understood
as the simple fact that human beings have a necessarily finite life-span,
that all human lives will come to an end at some point. Rather, to describe
human beings as mortal is to point out that every moment of human life
contains the threat of the end of that life; every mortal moment is necessarily
riven with the possibility of its own non-existence. Death is not an abstract
or distant limit to life, an indeterminate but inevitable boundary to
the succession of days, but rather a presence in every present moment
of our existence. This is an interpretation of the human relationship
to death which Heidegger captures in his notion of human existence as
Being-towards-death; and in the context of this film, its emergence reveals
the ultimate irrelevance of any distinction between human beings and replicants
which is couched in terms of the length of their respective life spans
or the degree of certainty with which each can predict an end to their
lives on a particular date. Both are alive, and both possess consciousness;
it follows that both will die, and that both are conscious of that fact.
Whether either will attain a grasp of the full significance of their mortality
and be capable of responding authentically to that significance is another
matter; but it is an issue which is as pertinent to replicants as it is
to human beings which is simply another way of saying that replicants
stand in a human relationship towards death.
Thus, whilst Deckard explores the significance and reflexivity of acknowledgement,
Roy engages in a quest for a correct understanding of mortality. Since,
as we have already noted, he interprets mortality as the condition of
having a finite life-span, and since he interprets that finitude as a
constraint (a very human reaction), he concludes that the only way to
master or transcend his mortality is to master or transcend its limits
by altering or extending the span of his life; and it is this conclusion
which leads him to Tyrell. We can see in advance that such a response
to human mortality constitutes a denial rather than an acknowledgement
of it; for the logical conclusion to which Roy's response points is the
removal of any temporal limit to one's life-span i.e. the attainment of
immortality and that condition is precisely the one in contrast to which
this interpretation of mortality is initially understood. It is only through
his encounter with Tyrell with his Maker that Roy comes to see the inadequacy
of his response, and to glimpse the possibility of a more authentic attitude
to his own mortality.
It becomes clear at once to Tyrell that Roy is misconceiving this critical
issue when his creation demands more life and asks if the Maker can repair
what he made as if the finitude of his life-span constituted essential
damage to his life. Tyrell engages in a brief discussion of the bio-mechanical
limitations on extending that life-span in just the way a doctor might
discuss the everyday human aging process but then dismisses the whole
topic ("All of this is academic.") and introduces the two central
notions this film will advance as ingredients of an authentic attitude
towards human mortality:
Tyrell: "He who burns twice as brightly burns half as long. And
you have burned so very very brightly, Roy... Revel in your time."
Roy: "I've done things questionable things."
Tyrell: "Nothing the God of bio-mechanics would not let you in
heaven for."
The metaphor of burning, by emphasizing brightness rather than duration,
encapsulates the idea that it is not the length but the quality of a life
that determines its value or worth; and here, quality of life relates
not to creature comforts but to the intensity with which one experiences
each moment of life as it occurs. This intensity is a function of the
way in which the relevant person recognizes the nature of time a recognition
which Heidegger embedded in his concept of authentic Being-towards-Death;
the transitory nature of the present is not taken to show its insignificance
or to lead to a form of life in which one ignores the present in favor
of living in the future or dwelling upon the past, for such attitudes
ignore the point that all experience is present experience and have the
consequence that the person involved fails entirely to engage with his
life as he lives it. Rather, the present moment is to be acknowledged
as a gift from the future and as destined to fade into the past facets
of the structure of time which serve to define the nature of the present,
but which should lead to a valuing of each present moment as it passes
rather than to its devaluation. Authentic human existence involves living
in the present and for the present without forgetting the way in which
the present is related to past and future; to live one's life as it should
be lived is to let every moment burn brightly and yet still acknowledge
that each moment will pass.
Tyrell goes on in the dialogue quoted above to advise Roy to revel in
his time. The Nietzschean connotations of the concept of revelry or play
should be evident here, particularly with the ensuing death of Roy's God:
Zarathustra speaks constantly of the overman as one who dances through
life, whose life is a dance and is invested with lightness and grace.
I take this scene to be positing a connection here between Nietzsche's
vision and the Heideggerian concept of the authentic Being-towards-Death:
the man who revels in life revels in each present moment, living it to
the full whilst respecting its essential nature as one transitory element
in the ineluctable stream of time. It is a notion which Roy is already
dimly aware of: in the immediately preceding scene, with Pris in J. F.
Sebastian's apartment, he responds to Pris' recitation of the Cartesian
dictum "I think therefore I am" by saying: "Very good,
Pris now show him why" and Pris performs a cartwheel, immediately
followed by plucking an egg from boiling water bare-handed. Roy knows,
in other words, that the mere fact of existence is not enough; fully living
one's life involves revelling in the possibilities of act and performance
that the fact of embodied existence makes possible.
Another way of expanding this claim about play or revelry in time would
be to say that the significance or meaning of the moments which go to
make one's life should be generated from within that life rather than
from a reliance upon external guarantors. The life of the overman, for
Zarathustra, was to be authenticated by means of the doctrine of eternal
recurrence: one had achieved a fully human life only if, when faced with
the chance to have one's life over again, one could sincerely desire that
not a single moment within it should be changed. Such a vision clearly
presupposes that one's life be a wholly integral unity, its parts hanging
together in a self-sufficient pattern from which nothing could be dislodged;
and such a self-sufficient life could have no need for sources of value
or worth external to itself it would be self-authenticating. To posit
such a life as fully human is thus to reject any necessity to refer to
the Christian God in its usual and essential role as guarantor of human
values; indeed, insofar as the presence of this God tempts and permits
men to think that they may refer the worth of their lives to Him, it becomes
essential for the attainment of a fully human life that God's presence
be removed from the scene. In narrating this removal as the murder of
God by men, Nietzsche is emphasizing in as graphic a way as possible the
need for men to accept full responsibility for their lives and for the
significance of those lives; and by inscribing himself into this narrative
by enacting the murder of his Creator in a way which brings an anguished
"Oh, my God!" from J. F. Sebastian Roy is assuming the mantle
of the overman. He has learnt his lesson, and he proves it by enacting
the most central of its corollaries the murder of his teacher.
Naturally enough, he wishes to pass on his discovery to the last remaining
replicant his lover, Pris. Deckard, however, gets there first and thus
(unwittingly) ensures that Roy will impart his good news in the form of
a final, practical lesson through which Deckard will acquire the capacity
to acknowledge the full humanity in Rachael and in himself. If, that is,
he survives the lesson.
On the one level, it seems that Roy's pursuit of Deckard through the
decaying building is motivated purely by revenge revenge not only for
the execution of Pris but also for the death of the other replicants:
Deckard carries their memory with him during his agonized feats of endurance
in the pain of broken fingers. Many other themes are woven together in
this climactic hunt, however; to begin with, Roy's role as overman is
repeatedly emphasized by the various ways in which he is presented as
having gone beyond good and evil not in the sense of having transcended
all notions of morality, but in the Nietzschean sense of having escaped
from the specifically Christian ethical code which is based upon a contrast
of good with evil rather than with bad. Roy draws attention to this aspect
of his role by characterizing Deckard as the representative of good ("I
thought you were supposed to be good aren't you the good man.") and
then hunting him down until he has experienced to the full "... what
it is to be a slave," i.e. what Roy conceives to be the essence of
a life dominated by Christian slave-morality. The Christian imagery which
gradually collects around Roy in this sequence the nail through the palm,
the frieze of cruciform ventilation units on the roof-top, the dove of
peace should thus be seen in part as a means of revealing the distance
Roy has moved beyond the morality expressed in such symbols: they are
available for him to use or discard as he sees fit, as tools for his own
personal purposes (he crucifies himself with the nail in order to delay
the decay of his body), and his use of them in the task of inculcating
a very non-Christian set of values in his pupil stakes a claim that his
message is at least as important for humanity as was Christ's. The hubris
of this last claim, the depths of self-assurance it requires, place Roy
firmly in the role of the noble, self-reliant re-evaluator of all values.
The concept of slavery acquires a further level of significance in this
sense, however: for at the end of Deckard's ordeal, after Roy's unexpected
rescue of him Roy offers his pupil the following description of his experience:
"Quite an experience to live in fear, isn't it? That's what it is,
to be a slave." The deliberate echoing of a phrase Leon chose to
describe the state of mind he was attempting to create in Deckard through
a savage beating makes it clear that the replicants have experienced their
own existence as one of living in fear an existence they define as slavery.
If we remember that replicants were specifically created to serve as expendable
substitutes for human beings in dangerous or dirty situations off-world,
and recall the time-honored view that slavery by annihilating the autonomy
of an individual destroys one's humanity, then it becomes obvious that
the human race as a whole is here indicted for the crime of denying the
humanity of its replicant servants. Deckard's ordeal places him on the
edge of existence and reduces him to an animal desire to survive; but
this minutes-long experience is merely a sample of the texture of which
all replicant life consists and the responsibility for that lies with
every human being.
Nevertheless, it seems undeniable that the central theme of this sequence
is death or, more precisely, the threat of death. Roy manipulates the
situation in such a way that Deckard comes to feel that every moment may
be his last, and Deckard's response to this is to flee from the threat.
Until the final confrontation with Roy, who assumes the status of the
Angel of Death for the blade runner, Deckard functions at the level of
an injured animal, incapable of anything more than an unthinking attempt
to avoid the threat of extinction by refusing to face it, by running away
from it. In this respect, he differs completely from his pursuer, who
it is important to remember is equally close to the edge of his own existence;
Roy knows and his malfunctioning hand confirms that his time is almost
up, and he is also aware that Deckard (when armed with gun or crowbar)
is perfectly capable of killing or seriously injuring him. The replicant's
response to this threat, however, is not to run from it but to run towards
it: in toying with Deckard, he also toys with the threat of extinction
which paralyzes Deckard's own capacity to transcend animal fear.
We are thus presented with two opposing ways of responding to a threat
of death; and, given the already-established Heideggerian and Nietzschean
background, we are justified in reading this sequence as a contrast between
authentic and unauthentic ways of living a human life for the defining
feature of human mortality is that every moment of existence is riven
with the necessary possibility of its non-existence; the threat these
men symbolize to one another is one which all human beings have woven
into the fabric of their everyday lives, and which they must acknowledge
or deny in some particular way. Deckard's response is unauthentic because
it is an attempt to deny the ubiquity of this threat; his flight from
Roy implies that if he can escape from this avenging replicant he will
be safe, he can escape from the threat of death an implication which constitutes
a denial of his own mortality. Roy's response, on the other hand, is authentic,
for he treats these matters of death and the death of love (Pris) playfully.
His cry of mourning over Pris is translated into a mock wolf-howl, an
imitation of the huntsman's pack which signals that the game (of life
and death) is afoot, and from that moment, his words and behavior are
shot through with the imagery of sport and play. He points out that firing
upon an unarmed man is not very sporting, and chides Deckard for unsportsmanlike
attacks with an iron bar; his response to one such attack, indeed, is
to cry "That's the spirit!" as if his protagonist is at last
beginning to play the game properly. The most important stretch of dialogue,
however, is the following one:
Roy: "You'd better get it up, or I'm going to have to kill you.
Unless you're alive, you can't play, and if you can't play..."
This emphasis upon sport is not (only) a sign of mania or psychological
imbalance, but rather a conjuration of the Nietzschean vision of revelry
or play as the authentic mode of mortal existence: like Zarathustra's
disciples, Roy is dancing on the edge of the abyss. It recalls Pris' demonstration
to J. F. Sebastian of the point of being alive by performing a cartwheel.
To play is to be fully alive, and part of investing one's life with such
lightness and grace is the capacity to look at death, and the death of
love, without fear or hysteria. Roy's way of conducting his life-and-death
duel with Deckard confirms his achievement of the status of overman.
He wants to do more than achieve this status for himself, however he
wants to teach Deckard how to achieve it as well. If Deckard fails to
absorb the lesson, he loses his chance to flourish as a human being: for
if to play is to be fully alive, not to play is to fail to live fully
one's humanity withers; and in such circumstances, with Deckard remaining
in his unauthentic form of life, Roy's threat to execute him would function
as little more than the public confirmation of a self- inflicted extinction
of what was human in him. If you can't play, you might as well be dead.
Deckard allows his suddenly-heightened awareness of the omnipresent possibility
of death to paralyze his life and reduce that life to animal instincts;
this response is unauthentic because, in effect, it transforms a possibility
into an actuality it permits that possibility to extinguish life by voiding
it of what is distinctively human, of an active embodied existence which
transcends the animal. Roy has the task of teaching Deckard the difference
between possibility and actuality; he does so by allowing him to spend
long minutes on the edge of his existence, by pushing him to the edge
of the abyss, by making death seem unavoidable and then rescuing him.
Rather than permitting death to swallow up and dominate one's life, an
authentic acknowledgement of one's Being-towards-death involves treating
death playfully for that is a way of acknowledging its omnipresent threat,
of showing that since the possibility of death is a defining characteristic
of human mortality (of what it means to be human) it is not something
one can or should avoid or deny.
Authenticity in this respect involves revelling or play in time, i.e.
revelling in each present moment, living it to the full whilst respecting
its essential nature as one transitory element in the ineluctable stream
of time. This is the insight Roy bequeaths to Deckard in the last moments
of the replicant's life, as they sit at the edge of their abyss:
Roy: "I've seen things you people wouldn't believe ... All those
moments will be lost in time, like tears in rain."
"Time to die."
Roy expresses the most seductive reason for wishing to postpone, avoid
or deny one's death the fact that rare and precious human experiences
are irrevocably lost with the death of the person who experienced them.
The loss is undeniable: and the film is surely right in the elegiac note
it strives for at this point; but the irrevocability of that loss is equally
undeniable. It would clearly count as a radical failure of acknowledgement
of the nature of human experience to avoid the truth that every present
moment will and must become a memory; the present can only be lived to
the full by respecting both its reality and its transitory nature. It
would, however, count as a further and more profound failure to wish to
bequeath one's own experience and memories to others as if one could outlive
oneself, as if one's moments of consciousness were alienable or transferable,
as if one's mortality could be denied. This point, too, achieves its clearest
articulation with respect to our relation to the moment of our death;
as Heidegger puts it, our death is inalienable no one can experience another
person's death for him, just as no one can die our death for us. Authentic
Being-towards-death thus involves a capacity to acknowledge and accept
the moment of our death, when it comes, as the own-most possibility of
our Being; Roy's calm and moving last words manifest just this authenticity,
and they cry our for acknowledgement as such.
It is Deckard as Roy's only companion upon whom that responsibility falls,
the obligation not merely to acknowledge the significance of those last
words but also to acknowledge them as last words, i.e. as part of Roy's
last moments. Deckard blinks, as if to clear his vision, and then provides
Roy with an epitaph:
Deckard: "Maybe he loved life more than he ever had before. All
he wanted were the same answers any of us want ... All I could do was
sit there and watch him die."
As an expression of acknowledgement of Roy as a fully human being, these
words could not be bettered. Deckard sees that his opponent's nature is
riven with precisely the same doubts and worries, loves and mysteries,
as his own; but in particular he sees that it is his task to sit there
and watch Roy die, i.e. that Roy is fully subject to the constraints of
human mortality, that his death is his own, and that the only and the
best way in which another human being can acknowledge Roy's humanity in
those moments is not to try hysterically to postpone his death, or to
try incoherently to take Roy's death upon himself, but rather to watch
that death and to watch it as the death of another human being. To acknowledge
someone's death is to acknowledge them as an entity whose essence is Being-towards-death,
but to acknowledge it in a way which recognizes that each person's death
is his own reveals insight and authenticity in the beholder: Deckard has
learned his lesson, about acknowledging others and about mortality, by
acknowledging another's death. As Inspector Gaff puts it, he has done
a man's job, the task of a human being, and Roy's bequest to Deckard culminates
in the resurrection of Rachael. It's a pity she won't live but then again,
who does?
2) What Becomes of People On Film?
The physical and spiritual landscape of Blade Runner is that of the
age of technology: those remnants of humanity left behind by the off-world
pioneers and settlers find themselves in a world with no sunlight, surrounded
by mechanisms huge, soulless buildings, police vehicles observing their
deeds from the air, flying advertisement hoardings with probing searchlights,
and obscurely purposeful but aberrantly shaped monoliths dividing up the
pavements and roadways. In every case, the scale of the machines dwarfs
that of their human creators, a diminution which is only restored by the
numbers of human beings who populate the city the ebb and flow of crowds
is alone capable of making it seem that Los Angeles is inhabited by its
people; but even within those crowds, it seems clear that technology threatens
its human creators in some intimate way.
This threat is bodied forth and stalks the streets in the form of the
replicants: they are seen by the Tyrell Corporation as the pinnacle of
human scientific achievement, and presented in the film as manifesting
a self-reliance which requires none of the technological crutches with
which the "real" human beings surround themselves; and the possibility
that any of these slaves might be loose on Earth calls forth an extremity
of response from their masters that transforms the replicants into the
stuff of nightmare. The police department, the blade runner units, the
cumbersome Voight-Kampff procedure all are brought into the campaign to
keep the planet unpolluted, as if the real but limited threat posed by
malfunctioning machines were in reality the first signs of a contagious
disease, of a plague. As figures in the psychic life of the humans stranded
in Los Angeles, the replicants are not a threat solely because of their
martial skills or physical perfections; as emblems of the technological
carapace with which human life is protected and mummified, they signify
a threat to the spiritual integrity the humanity of these remnants of
the human race. The future that they fear is evident in their offspring:
in the low hiss of wheels as a swarm of children glide by on their bikes,
in the jabbering city-speak arguments they have over machinery stolen
from stationary vehicles, in the distorting layers of material wrapped
around their small heads and bodies, these gangs of street-urchins embody
the dehumanized future of mankind on its machine-ridden planet.
The question of whether human flourishing is possible in such an age
is one which this film insistently poses, but it does so in a very specific
way. To understand this, we need to remember that, of all art forms, that
of film-making is the most inherently dependent upon technology. The material
basis of film is the recording capacity of the camera, i.e. the automatic
production of an image of the world which is exhibited before the camera
lens, and the consequent reproduction and projection of that image onto
a cinema screen. One might say that the camera seems to satisfy one of
mankind's perennial fantasies that of recording the way the world is without
the mediation or distortion consequent upon the interposition of human
subjectivity into the recording process <2>.
One could then go on to say that the attempt to make a film to utilize
the camera for artistic purposes constitutes an attempt to find a possibility
of human flourishing within the heart of the humanly threatening age of
technology, to subvert that threat from the inside. Certainly, Blade Runner
takes the question of whether human flourishing is possible in such an
age to be answered by answering the question of whether a film (more specifically
the film Blade Runner) can be a work of art.
As it stands, however, this question is both unmotivated (why should
any open-minded person doubt that a film-maker can create a work of art?)
and excessively general (what criteria should we use to test whether any
given film is a work of art?). We require a further pointer concerning
the nature of technology and of its era if we are to grasp the reasons
for this cinematic self-doubt (as it were); and once again Heidegger can
be of some use here. In an essay entitled "The Age of Technology,"
<3> he
identified the Zeitgeist of our age as the tendency to treat the natural
world as a store of resources and raw materials for human purposes to
regard rivers as hydro-electric power sources, forests as a standing reserve
of paper, the winds as currents of potential energy; this attitude he
contrasted with that of acknowledging and respecting nature as a field
of objects, forces and living beings each with their own specific essence
or Being a being which humans alone were capable of coming to understand
and thereby coming to fulfill more fully their own Being (namely Dasein
that being for which an understanding of Being is an issue). This analysis
might lead any film-maker to doubt the purity of film as an art-form a
mode of human flourishing because Heidegger's chosen label for the fatefully
destructive attitude of treating nature as a standing reserve is "enframing;"
and this phraseology recalls that earlier description of the process of
automatically producing, reproducing and projecting an image of the world
which we have already utilized as a means of characterizing the operations
of the camera. For Heidegger, the fate of mankind and the essence of humanity
hang on the task of transcending the attitude of enframing; for a film-maker,
confronted with the knowledge that his role is precisely to take responsibility
for enframing the world, for meaning the composition and exclusion constituted
by each frame in his film, that task of transcendence is logically excluded
and he is left with the awareness that the means he wishes to employ in
preserving humanity and human flourishing may be essentially self-
defeating.
Once the possibility of the inherent dehumanizing potential of film is
raised, however, the subject-matter by means of which one might most clearly
test that possibility becomes clear; for if the camera's enframing of
the natural world constitutes a denial of the essence of that world and
thus a denial of the viewer's essentially human capacity to acknowledge
that essence, then this dehumanizing threat would surely become most potent
and most evident when the camera turns to frame human beings on film.
In such circumstances, where humanity is precisely what is being put before
the camera, the possibility of framing that humanity without loss and
our capacity as viewers to perceive that humanity in the frames of the
film would receive their most fundamental test. Of course, the successful
framing of humanity on film could not guarantee that this humanity be
acknowledged by the viewer, for in one respect our position as viewers
resembles that of Deckard in the specific film we are discussing: just
as Deckard is able to see that in every relevant way the replicants are
suitable candidates for personhood but must still make the leap of acknowledgement,
so any film viewer is presented with a world which may confirm in every
possible way that the objects of his vision include human beings but which
cannot force him to acknowledge their humanity. The major difference from
Deckard lies in the fact that the blade runner cannot off-load any of
his responsibility onto a director whose enframing decisions create the
world he sees.
Success in filming such subject-matter (i.e. the creation of a filmed
world which was such that any failure to acknowledge the humanity of the
filmed characters would be the responsibility of the viewer) would then
constitute an artistic proof that the age of technology is incapable of
completely obliterating human flourishing or, more precisely, that it
is humanly possible to produce a film that is a work of art. The question
Blade Runner therefore takes it upon itself to answer is: what becomes
of people on film?
Let us now try to assemble some of the evidence suggesting that Blade
Runner is indeed a film about film (making). The theme is announced in
its opening sequence, in which the gradual approach of the camera towards
the Tyrell building and the room in which Leon is being interrogated is
inter-cut with close-ups of an unblinking eye, one in which the venting
flames of the city-scape surrounding the Tyrell buildings wash in reflection
across the pupil and iris; this all-seeing, unblinking eye seems to me
to be an obvious image for the camera which is directing and focusing
our gaze as viewers. The film never identifies it as belonging to any
of the characters in the story, and the incident upon which this sequence
eventually focuses Leon's interrogation by and execution of a blade runner
is presented to those characters in the form of a video or film recording.
Since we are presented with this incident at first hand (as it were),
the later representations of it in the form of a film serve only to emphasize
further the presence of the camera as mediator between the viewer and
the events viewed.
The character who is presented as obsessively viewing and reviewing this
film-within-the-film is Deckard; and when this fact is taken together
with the early scene in which (alongside Bryant) he sits in a darkened
room or theater observing photographs of the replicants projected on a
screen before him as if viewing the rushes of a film or considering editing
options then the film's posited identification of Deckard with a director
(more specifically with the director of a film about replicants) begins
to emerge. This identification is confirmed by two central features of
his job as a blade runner or detective: first, his use of the Voight-Kampff
machine, a construction which involves his looking at people through a
view finder and controlling the focus of the machine's gaze on their faces;
and secondly, his use of the televisual unit in his apartment to unearth
evidence of Zhora in Leon's life this feat of detection involves analysis
of a photograph, but more precisely it involves directing the focus of
analysis within the photograph, calling for close-ups and tracking shots
within the photographed room as if it were a film set.
If this interpretative claim is correct, then it is already clear that
this film shows itself to be aware of the destructive potential inherent
in framing humanity on film, for the choice of a blade runner as directorial
surrogate brings into the foreground precisely this dehumanizing potential
it is one aspect of Deckard's business to elucidate signs of non-humanity
from the people upon whom his attention focuses, and if he performs his
job correctly his attention focuses on replicants and results in their
execution. This sense of the death dealing potential of film is further
emphasized by the film's identification of the camera with a gun: since
Deckard fulfills the role of director, his progress throughout the film
behind an advancing gun and, in particular, his progress through the Bradbury
building in search of Pris and Roy, during which he rigidly holds his
weapon in front of him as if it were mediating his vision of the environment
as a whole manifests a claim that the director's professional equipment
is a potentially lethal weapon.
As we have already had cause to emphasize, however, potentiality and
actuality are two very different things, particularly when it is death
that is at stake; after all, Deckard doesn't actually execute Rachael
in the elevator when she surprises him there at the beginning of the film.
To put this more precisely: Blade Runner offers more than one surrogate
for the camera, since another piece of equipment which plays a key role
in Deckard's job and through which he tends to focus upon people he encounters
is the Voight-Kampff machine which we have already mentioned. This piece
of technology can, of course, help to issue a sentence of death, but its
primary function is not to dehumanize whatever is placed in front of it
but rather to assess the humanity of those subject to its gaze its purpose
is to bring out or elucidate any humanity which might be there, as well
as revealing inhumanity if it is present. If we identify the camera with
such a machine, then we must read the film as claiming that the camera's
capacity to destroy the human in what it captures is matched by a capacity
to preserve that same quality.
If these remarks suffice to establish the claim that the question of
what becomes of (the humanity of) people on film is an explicit concern
of this film, then what answer can we regard it as returning to its own
question? This answer is manifest in the scene after Roy's death when
Deckard returns to his apartment and to Rachael. Once again, Deckard's
entrance involves viewing the world along the barrel of his gun, and when
the camera reveals Rachael under a sheet/shroud, it seems clear that the
death-dealing properties of the director's art have won out. Such is not
the case, however: for Deckard removes the shroud with his gun and Rachael
comes back from the dead. The point, I think, is this: although the camera
(like a gun) has an inherent death-dealing capacity (guns are after all
made for killing), its dehumanizing tendency can be subverted and the
life of its human subjects preserved, but this possibility of subversion
depends upon the manner in which the camera is used. As we noted earlier,
the camera can be seen as a means of recording the way the world is without
the interposition of human subjectivity into the recording process; but
one of the central claims of our particular film is that the flourishing
of any person's humanity requires its acknowledgement by those who observe
(or otherwise interact with) him and this entails that human subjectivity
must be interposed, must play a role, if humanity is to be preserved on
film. The goal of preserving this humanity thus involves working against
the grain of the process of filming, which is why the camera is in the
end identified with a gun rather than with the inherently neutral Voight-Kampff
machine; but the resurrection of Rachael also records this director's
conviction that the grain of film can indeed be opposed and worked against.
What this means is that it is not just the fact of enframing but also
the way that enframing is done which determines what becomes of the human
on film. To put it another way: the responsibility for preserving or destroying
the humanity of the camera's subjects rests with the particular director;
if he abdicates from his responsibility to recognize and elicit the humanity
of filmed people, then the camera will transform those subjects into objects
(into replicants), but if he exercises that responsibility adequately,
then he retains the power to vivify their subjectivity (as Deckard learns
to do with Rachael). It follows that, just as an individual's achievement
of humanity in this respect cannot be evaluated apart from the nature
of his relationships with particular people and their development over
time, so how any director exercises his responsibilities and what he achieves
by means of their exercise cannot be predicted in advance of an assessment
of each particular film he makes. A gun can be used to kill or to remove
a shroud; the choice and the responsibility rest with the person holding
the gun, and are manifest in each particular thing he does with it.
Blade Runner does, however, offer a certain set of suggestions about
how a director must exercise his responsibilities if he is to preserve
rather than destroy the humanity of his filmed subjects: for Deckard's
capacity to use his gun/camera to resurrect Rachael is entirely due to
the lesson Roy teaches him. This lesson begins with Deckard losing his
gun, his badge of director's rank as if losing the symbol of his distinction
from the rest of humanity, as if part of his lesson is that being a good
director involves no more (and no less) than permitting his definitively
human capacities to flourish and be expressed. This interpretation is
confirmed by the lesson Roy goes on to teach, for as we have seen Deckard
is taught to acknowledge the humanity of others, understood as an acknowledgement
of their mortality and finitude; and he learns in addition that a failure
to acknowledge the humanity of others is a way of crippling one's own
humanity, of creating a spiritual blankness. Blade Runner therefore claims
two things about the task of directing: first, that to preserve the humanity
of the camera's subjects is an achievement of human flourishing in itself;
and secondly, that a failure to do so a failure to make a film which is
a work of art is a failure of humanity in the director.
Film-making thus presents itself as no more (and no less) than a specific
way in which one human being can acknowledge or fail to acknowledge the
humanity of others a challenge which faces us all in every moment of our
lives. The camera's potential for dehumanizing its subjects can be matched
by its capacity to translate them into screened images with their humanity
preserved, and so it cannot provide the director with a scapegoat upon
which to load the responsibility for a failure of acknowledgement or with
a crutch which makes authentic acknowledgement any easier to achieve.
This truth about the responsibilities of the director does not, however,
remove the responsibilities of the viewer. The camera if responsibly utilized
by the director may show us all the evidence, all the facts of the matter,
everything that is the case and that may be relevant to evaluating the
humanity of its subjects, but it cannot acknowledge their humanity for
us. That remains the task of the viewer.
Notes
<1>
Cf the detailed treatment of these themes in his book The Claim of Reason
(OUP, Oxford: 1979).
<2>
For more detail on this issue, cf Stanley Cavell, The World Viewed (Harvard
University Press, Cambridge MA: 1971).
<3>
Collected in Poetry, Language, Thought (Harper and Row, New York: 1971),
trans. A. Hofstadter.
Copyright © Dr Stephen Mulhall
Published by BRmovie.com in the
Blade Runner and DADoES Analysis Section
This
analysis is the original article as published on the Web.
Dr Mulhall has now revised this article to become part of chapter one
of his book 'On
Film' (Routledge, 2002).
|